




|
Ancient
Philosophy
The Presocratics – Pythagoras and Xenophanes
Primary Sources:
- Pythagoras and Xenophanes, Fragments from Baird and Kaufmann, Ancient
Philosophy, pp. 11-15.
- Pythagoras and Xenophanes, Additional Fragments (Handout).
Background:
From Hermann S. Schibli’s Routlegde Online Encyclopedia
article on Pythagoras:
Pythagoras of Samos was an early Greek sage and religious innovator.
He taught the kinship of all life and the immortality and transmigration
of the soul. Pythagoras founded a religious community of men and women
in southern Italy that was also of considerable political influence.
His followers, who became known as Pythagoreans, went beyond these essentially
religious beliefs of the master to develop philosophical, mathematical,
astronomical, and musical theories with which they tended to credit
Pythagoras himself. The tradition established by Pythagoras weaves through
much of Greek philosophy, leaving its mark particularly on the thought
of Empedocles, Plato, and later Platonists.
Pythagoras, son of Mnesarchus, was born on the island of Samos. For
the first half of his life Pythagoras traveled widely, not only in Greece
but supposedly also in Egypt, Phoenicia and Babylonia, where he is reputed
to have acquired much of his knowledge and religious wisdom. Perhaps
to escape the rule of Polycrates, the tyrant of Samos, he emigrated
to Croton in southern Italy. His moral stature and eloquence gained
him many adherents. With his followers, both men and women, Pythagoras
practiced a simple, communal life whose goal was to live in harmony
with the divine. To that end he prescribed a regimen of purification
that included dietary restrictions, periods of silence and contemplation,
and other ascetic practices. In addition to the religious and monastic
aspects of the Pythagorean society, we hear of Pythagorean political
associations (hetaireiai) that played an important role in the public
affairs of Croton and other southern Italian cities (it appears they
initiated social reforms and supported aristocratic constitutions).
After a time their dominance came to be resented and a ‘Pythagorean
revolt’ ensued, in the course of which many Pythagoreans were
killed or scattered abroad. Pythagoras himself, possibly as a result
of this upheaval, moved to Metapontum where he died.
Already during his lifetime Pythagoras was regarded with near religious
veneration. It is therefore not surprising that the stories told about
him after his death should turn into hagiology and include many fantastic
elements: that Pythagoras was the Hyperborean Apollo and had a golden
thigh to prove it; that he was seen in two places at one time; that
he could converse with animals and control natural phenomena. Pythagoras’
wonder-working clearly belongs to the realm of legend, although it reinforces
the picture of him as a ‘shaman’. A more difficult matter
is to establish what Pythagoras actually taught, since the oral and
then the written traditions attribute to him not only miracles but also
sophisticated mathematical and philosophical achievements. This habit
of tracing all things back to the master, coupled with evidence of the
quasi-religious avoidance of uttering his name, is typified in the expression
common among Pythagoreans: ‘he himself said’. However, because
Pythagoras wrote nothing and shrouded his lectures in secrecy, it is
impossible to verify all that is ascribed to him. What remains certain
is that he was a highly influential religious teacher whose main tenets
dealt with the soul and the rites required for its purification and
salvation. This made the Pythagorean movement especially popular in
Magna Graecia, a fertile soil for mystery cults of all kinds. Pythagoras
is also connected with certain ‘Orphic’ writings, since
these share eschatological concerns similar to his oral teachings. For
these reasons the following account will emphasize those doctrines that
accord with Pythagoras’ reputation as an early Greek sage and
religious innovator (for the philosophical and scientific theories traditionally
associated with his name).
From J. H. Lesher’s Routlegde Online Encyclopedia article
on Xenophanes:
 |
|
Xenophanes was a philosophically minded poet who lived in various cities
of ancient Greece. He is best remembered for an early comment on the
limits of knowledge, a critique of anthropomorphism in religion and
an advance towards monotheism. The surviving fragments of his poems
span a wide range of topics, from proper behavior at symposia and the
measures of personal excellence to the nature of the divine, the forces
that rule nature and how much can be discovered by mortals concerning
matters in either realm. Both Plato and Aristotle characterized him
as the founder of Eleatic philosophy, a view echoed in the pseudo-Aristotelian
treatise, On Melissus, Xenophanes and Gorgias, and in ancient
doxographical summaries. But in many of his poems Xenophanes speaks
as a civic counselor and inquirer into nature in the tradition of the
philosopher-scientists of Miletus. While his one, unmoving, whole and
eternal divinity bears some resemblance to Parmenides’ ‘being’,
in other teachings he anticipates the views of Heraclitus and Empedocles.
His comments on divine perfection, the limited utility of the victorious
athlete and the need to restrict poetic expression all foreshadow views
expressed by Plato in the Republic.
Ancient reports of his contacts with other philosophers are few and
inconclusive, but the reference to a puppy which possessed the soul
of a friend shows some awareness of Pythagorean teachings and the remarks
about earth, sun, sea, waters and rainbow display an interest in matters
investigated by the Milesians. Herodotus reports Xenophanes’ ‘admiration’
or ‘wonder’ (or perhaps ‘amazement’) regarding
Thales’ successful prediction of a solar eclipse; Heraclitus disparages
him as a (mere) polymath; and Empedocles challenges the view of the
earth’s ‘unlimited’ depths expressed in Xenophanes.
Xenophanes wrote in verse, a fact which reflects both his chosen profession
and an age that drew no sharp distinction between poet, sage and teacher.
Most of his poems eschew complex argument in favor of simple and emphatic
dissent but employ hypothetical suppositions or ‘thought experiments’
to establish unnoticed contrasts and connections, and the different
aspects of his teachings can be placed within a coherent overall scheme.
He is the first Greek philosopher for whom an appreciable body of work
has survived, but his difficult terminology and phrasing, along with
the conflicting ancient testimonia, have spawned radically different
interpretations of his teachings and sharply divergent appraisals of
his importance as a thinker.
Questions:
- How is Pythagoras different from the other Pre-Socratics we have
read so far? How is he similar?
- What contributions did Pythagoras make in mathematics? How is mathematics
similar to naturalism? How does he take mathematics to extremes when
discussing justice?
- How does Pythagorean mysticism anticipate the Judea-Christian tradition?
- How is Xenophanes critical of the values of Greek society?
- How does Xenophanes conceive the relationship between knowledge and
opinion?
- How is Xenophanes critical of the Homeric conception of the gods?
How does he conceive of god instead?
I love Apache! So should you!
|
|